The Dangerous Rise Of Climate Litigation

I was once in the audience at a conference when a very senior member of the judiciary of a major developed nation declared off-handedly, in a response to a question, that: “Law is relevant to every single issue of human conduct.”

It was a revealing remark and I noted it down verbatim. I often think about it.

To somebody armed with a hammer, every problem looks like a nail; to the judge, every problem looks like a court case.

This is, I suppose, to be expected. And at that level the statement was almost oxymoronic.

But the comment also expressed something deeply important about modern societies.

The German social theorist Niklas Luhmann described such societies as being divided into distinct communicative systems (politics, law, economics, medicine, mass media and so on) wherein the environment – meaning the underlying real world – is processed by a system of code into a communicative format which is digestible to the system proper.

For the legal system, that code is ‘lawful/not lawful’: everything in the system’s environment must be understood in those terms, and the whole of reality (in the eyes of the legal system) is encompassed in that dynamic.

It follows of course that nothing can happen that cannot be thought of by the legal system on the basis of it being lawful/not lawful, legal/illegal. Anything and everything that has ever happened, or potentially could ever happen, is either one or the other.

Sooner or later, then, it was inevitable that the climate itself – the literal environment – would be subsumed within this logic, and that human interactions with the very world in which we live would become subject to this binary coding.

And so what was inevitable has indeed come to pass, in the form of two separate suites of litigation happening at opposite ends of the world, in Europe and New Zealand respectively.

One runs great risks when discussing the ins-and-outs of litigation that is ongoing. Judges can be unpredictable buggers. And one runs even greater risks in this regard when discussing litigation that falls to be decided imminently.

This post will go out on April 8th and it concerns three cases in which the judgments will be handed down on the 9th. Those of you who read the post in time will therefore be able to follow along in real time, as it were, and see how accurate my predictions were.

But, as I will emphasise towards the end of the post, in one important respect it actually doesn’t really matter what the outcomes are.

New Zealand first, then – land of lamb, pinot noir and weird names for rugby positions. In the recent case of Michael John Smith v Fronterra Cooperative Group Ltd and Ors [2024] NZSC 5, the Supreme Court of New Zealand overturned the decision of a lower court to strike out a claim (meaning, to deny a hearing) to a Maori elder who wanted to sue various New Zealand companies who were involved in the emission of ‘greenhouse gases’.

The idea here is that the ‘climate crisis’ is endangering lands of cultural and spiritual significance to this man’s clan, and that the emission of greenhouse gases is a civil wrong – a tort – which should provide him (and presumably his people) with a monetary remedy.

It’s either a public nuisance, negligence or an entirely new tort of “climate system damage”. The NZ Court of Appeal had earlier struck out the claim as being manifestly bound to fail – reasoning, I think pretty sensibly, that:

The magnitude of the crisis which is climate change simply cannot be appropriately or adequately addressed by common law tort claims pursued through the courts.

It is quintessentially a matter that calls for a sophisticated regulatory response at a national level supported by international co-ordination.

In other words, if one grants that ‘climate change’ is an issue which we will have to deal with in some respect (a position I agree with by and large), then that should happen through the democratic political process and not litigation.

It’s a matter for parliaments, not courts. And so the case should not be heard.

The Supreme Court disagreed. Declaring, ominously I think, that “the principles governing public nuisance ought not to stand still in the face of massive environmental challenges attributable to human economic activity”, it decided that the claim should proceed to a full hearing.

This does not mean it decided the issue one way or the other, but rather that said issue will now actually fall to be determined by a court (inevitably, ultimately, the Supreme Court itself). This will presumably happen later this year, although I am not familiar with the speed with which the wheels of justice turn down in Wellington.

Europe next – specifically Strasbourg, land of Eurocrats, Alsatian dogs and Franco-Prussian antagonism. The Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights will on April 9th 2024 hand down its decisions in the three conjoined cases of Verein KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz and Others v SwitzerlandCarême v France and Duarte Agostinho and Others v Portugal and 32 Others. 

In its judgments it will determine roughly the same issue as the NZ Supreme Court from the opposite direction, as it were. Whereas in Smith the dispute is in private law, and the claimant seeks compensation from the corporate defendants for the torts in question, in these cases the matter is one of public law: whether governments are breaching the human rights of their populations in failing to respond adequately to the aforementioned ‘climate crisis’.

In the first case, Verein KlimaSeniorinnen Schweiz, the applicants, a group of elderly women, have complained that the public authorities are not doing enough to prevent ‘climate change’s impacts on their living standards and health.

In the second, Carême, a former Mayor of a municipality in France is suing the state on the basis that ‘climate change’ represents a threat to his right to life and right to respect for his private and family life and not enough is being done to prevent it.

In the third, Duarte Agostinho and Others (which, I have to say, is possibly the most egregious example of human rights litigation that I have ever encountered, and I’ve seen a lot), a group of six Portuguese nationals aged between eight and 21 years old have brought a claim against pretty much every state in the Council of Europe, alleging that ‘climate change’ will “impact their lives, well-being, mental health and their homes” due to [checks notes] increased risk of heatwaves, wildfires and wildfire smoke.

This, they allege, will breach obligations they are owed with respect to their rights to [checks notes again] life, prohibition of ill-treatment, respect for private and family life and non-discrimination (on the basis that global warming will affect young people more than old).

Leaving aside the merits (or lack of such) of these four cases, what will be the outcome?

The vagaries of the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights are such that it is almost impossible to predict in advance what it will decide on any given issue, and while I would once have said that the Supreme Court of New Zealand can be expected to be pretty sensible, I have to say that genuinely nothing would surprise me these days.

All four cases could be laughed out of court, but, equally, all four could succeed.

What I think is most likely to happen – and we’ll find out in due course – is that the claimants in each case will fail, but that the court in question will not be able to resist the opportunity to ‘develop’ the law, and will hint that future claims, better made-out and better supported by evidence, may succeed.

The New Zealand Supreme Court will say something along the lines of: “While here the claim cannot succeed, we see no reason why in principle there shouldn’t be a tort of climate system damage.

And the European Court of Human Rights will say something like: “While here the claims cannot succeed, a future claimant might do so by proving x, y and z.” And the doors will be thereby left open for further litigation.

Whatever the courts in question decide, however, the important point is that these cases are being brought and heard in the first place. Because they really shouldn’t be. Indeed, one could hardly imagine a subject which, on the face of it, is less suitable for being decided in a court of law.

This is for three obvious reasons.

The first is that a court is supposed to apply, rather than make, law, and in this area there simply is no applicable law. There is no tort of “climate system damage” and nothing in the history of the law of tort resembles anything really like it.

The drafters of the European Convention of Human Rights had nothing like ‘climate change’ in mind when they came up with the treaty (though the Court has developed a complex doctrine, known as the ‘living instrument’ approach, or ‘evolutive interpretation’, to explain away this kind of problem).

If any of these cases succeed it will be because the court in question has in effect indulged in law-making from the bench, and this is not what is supposed to happen in a properly developed legal system.

The second reason is that courts lack political legitimacy (at least outside of the U.S., where judges are either political appointments or are actually elected). They are not accountable to the electorate directly or indirectly via elected politicians.

They should therefore not be the ones to be deciding important matters of policy, such as whether people who are affected by ‘climate change’ (assuming causation can be proved, which is a rather large assumption) are entitled to a remedy of some kind – let alone what that remedy should be.

And the third reason is that courts lack expertise in complex matters. I don’t mean this only in the sense that judges are not climate scientists; a committee of climate scientists would lack expertise in this regard too.

This is because the issues involved are ‘complex’ in the strict sense – they encompass a range of fields (science, economy, law, health, etc.), a range of sub-domains within those fields, a range of competing values, and a range of different priorities, and all of these different factors influence each other in unforeseeable ways.

Not only is it the case, then, that no single body of men and women could properly ‘expertly’ evaluate the issues involved. It is also the case that many of those issues (particularly underlying questions about values and morality) cannot reasonably be described as being subject to expertise at all.

No human being can be more of an expert than any other in what it is appropriate to value. The matters being litigated are, in other words, matters of politics par excellence – and politics is something that courts are very poorly equipped to do.

But this brings us, with a bump, back to Niklas Luhmann. Luhmann was an obscurantist and an elitist and he made his writing deliberately inaccessible (even for those with a good command of academic German, which I certainly do not have).

And I will here therefore somewhat bastardise and bowdlerise him to make an argument I am sure he would not have endorsed. But I will do this to draw out what I think, lurking in the background, was one of his important messages: that modernity would witness a kind of withering, or shrinking, of politics and its replacement by, among other things, law.

We can think of the political as the realm in which decisions are made through the application of power. If we’re lucky, that power derives from democratic legitimacy; it could of course just as well derive from the might of an autocrat.

The point, though, is that the power is executive: a wide range of factors – ideally all relevant factors – are weighed up, and a decision is reached on the basis of what is thought ‘best’, with what ‘best’ would look like being determined by the holder(s) of power.

Obviously, ideally, they have a good hold on what would actually be ‘best’ and exercise their decision-making power accordingly – they may very well not do.

Yet we live in societies in which the vast complexity of the underlying reality (the things that are actually present, that are actually happening) is absorbed into functionally differentiated social systems which repackage them on the basis of simple binaries: the legal system categorises everything into lawful/not lawful; the mass media system categorises everything into news/not news; the scientific system categorises everything into true/not true; the medical system categorises everything into healthy/not healthy, and so on.

The space for politics becomes smaller and smaller as a result, because the requirement for political decision-making as such is squeezed out in the face of the imperatives of the other social systems.

The classic example of this is of course COVID-19, in which, as you will remember, a new ‘happening’ bubbled up from the environment (the virus) and within a matter of weeks everybody seemed to ‘know’ about it in terms of what was news (wet market, terrible threat, new normal) and was not news (lab leak, early spread); what was ‘true’ (everybody is equally vulnerable, social distancing works) and what was ‘not true’ (old people are much more vulnerable than young people, social distancing is just theatre); what was lawful (stay at home) and what was not lawful (sunbathe, sit on a park bench, hug your grandmother at a funeral).

And all of this seemed to happen not on the basis of political decision-making in the sense that I outlined it earlier, but rather on the basis of a kind of collective communicative freak-out which encompassed politicians and non-politicians alike.

Politicians were not absent from the picture but they did not wield politics as such; they rather were blown about and buffeted by a whirlwind of intense communication (opinion polls, scientific reports, modelling forecasts, tweets, etc.) that overcame them.

The result was that the media, legal, medical and scientific systems staged a kind of undeclared revolt and went off on a wild frolic of their own – with the politicians trailing in the distance, trying to somehow keep up.

Something similar is going on, to a less dramatic extent, with these ‘climate change’ cases.

What to do about ‘climate change’, as I earlier said, has to be resolved through processes which are political: in which all relevant factors are weighed up and decisions are made by those in power – ideally, by those who are democratically accountable to the people.

What we are seeing instead is the legal system’s absorption of the issue into its own communicative framing, in which everything to do with the matter is reduced to a simple coding on the basis of what is lawful and what is not lawful.

See more here dailysceptic.org

Please Donate Below To Support Our Ongoing Work To Defend The Scientific Method

PRINCIPIA SCIENTIFIC INTERNATIONAL, legally registered in the UK as a company incorporated for charitable purposes. Head Office: 27 Old Gloucester Street, London WC1N 3AX. 

Trackback from your site.

Comments (1)

  • Avatar

    Wisenox

    |

    Laws are mutable; they don’t follow them. If the law is meaningless to those in power, then it’s meaningless to everyone else as well.

    Reply

Leave a comment

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.
Share via